TY - CHAP
T1 - Philosophical Background
AU - Agassi, Joseph
N1 - Publisher Copyright:
© 2013, Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.
PY - 2013
Y1 - 2013
N2 - This is a description of the background to classical physics, not a history of physics or of methodology. In the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century, researchers misinterpreted the history of the philosophy and of the science of their own time, and they misled later historians of science: later historians viewed these interpretations as first-hand evidence. Consequently, the largely unsatisfactory picture of classical science is almost unanimously received (Agassi 2008, 166). The misleading texts were always detached from their authors’ social background. Consequently, questions regarding the social background of science remained unasked. In the twentieth century the sociology of science became popular for reasons that had to do with contemporary science. This led historians of science to study the social background of science. The sociology of the rise of modern science remained hardly studied. Some Marxist scholars touched upon this matter, but their intent was only to reveal the socio-economic background to it, and from a Marxist viewpoint. Gideon Freudenthal and Peter McLaughlin have called this “the Hessen-Grossman-Thesis” (Freudenthal and McLaughlin 2009, 1). Thus, the famous Marxist crystallographer-turned-philosopher J. D. Bernal took for granted that mediaeval science was superior to ancient science (Agassi 2008, 222–3); this renders the renaissance ideology incomprehensible.
AB - This is a description of the background to classical physics, not a history of physics or of methodology. In the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century, researchers misinterpreted the history of the philosophy and of the science of their own time, and they misled later historians of science: later historians viewed these interpretations as first-hand evidence. Consequently, the largely unsatisfactory picture of classical science is almost unanimously received (Agassi 2008, 166). The misleading texts were always detached from their authors’ social background. Consequently, questions regarding the social background of science remained unasked. In the twentieth century the sociology of science became popular for reasons that had to do with contemporary science. This led historians of science to study the social background of science. The sociology of the rise of modern science remained hardly studied. Some Marxist scholars touched upon this matter, but their intent was only to reveal the socio-economic background to it, and from a Marxist viewpoint. Gideon Freudenthal and Peter McLaughlin have called this “the Hessen-Grossman-Thesis” (Freudenthal and McLaughlin 2009, 1). Thus, the famous Marxist crystallographer-turned-philosopher J. D. Bernal took for granted that mediaeval science was superior to ancient science (Agassi 2008, 222–3); this renders the renaissance ideology incomprehensible.
KW - Central Force
KW - Classical Science
KW - Metaphysical View
KW - Observation Sentence
KW - Social Background
UR - http://www.scopus.com/inward/record.url?scp=85101982568&partnerID=8YFLogxK
U2 - 10.1007/978-94-007-5351-8_10
DO - 10.1007/978-94-007-5351-8_10
M3 - ???researchoutput.researchoutputtypes.contributiontobookanthology.chapter???
AN - SCOPUS:85101982568
T3 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science
SP - 131
EP - 137
BT - Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science
PB - Springer Nature
ER -